Tuesday, December 18, 2012

NEVIS REVIEW NO 6 , Section II, Ref # 6.2

NEVIS REVIEW NO 6
Section II
 Ref # 6.2
Dec 17, 2012

Abstract of the article by Lisa Blaydes and James Lo, titled " One man, one vote, one time? A model of democratization in the Middle East", Journal of Theoretical Politics
------
The protests associated with the 2011 Arab Spring represent a serious and sustained challenge to autocratic rule in the Middle East. Under what conditions will Arab protest movements translate
into a full-fledged ‘fourth wave’ of democratization­? We argue that questions about the commitment of Islamic political opposition to democracy beyond a country’s first free election may hinder Middle Eastern democratization­. We extend Przeworski’s canonical model of political liberalization as described in Democracy and the Market (1991) and find that transition to democracy
is only possible under two conditions. First, uncertainty regarding the preferences of key elite actors is a necessary condition for democratic transition. Second, the repressive capacity of the
state must lie above a minimum threshold. Given these conditions, democracy can occur when two types of political actors meet – regime liberalizers who prefer democracy to a narrowed
dictatorship, and civil society elite who honor democratic principles. While a series of influential studies have argued that authoritarian elites block democratic transition because of their fear of the economic redistributive preferences of the median voter, this study suggests that regime liberalizers in the Middle East suspect political openings could become a vehicle for Islamists to seize power through free elections only to deny the median voter another chance to express their will.
---------------­----------
For full article, follow this link. http://­www.stanford.edu­/~blaydes/­Democracy.pdf

Monday, December 17, 2012

NEVIS REVIEW NO 6 , Section I,Ref # 6.1

NEVIS REVIEW NO 6
Section I
Ref # 6.1
Dec 17, 2012

Democracy and Political Culture
Part II-Background to Africa’s Democracy
 by Hiwot Wendimagegn

Liberal democracy, despite its claim of universality is historically specific. It is a child of industrial civilization, a product of a socially atomized society that has moved past the concerns of physical and economic survival to opt for “liberty”, “equality” and “the pursuit of happiness” (Ake, 1993:240). Along these lines, the principles of democracy include: widespread participation, the right of citizens to determine their form of government, citizen’s preferences being weighed relatively equally, consent of the governed and government’s accountability and responsiveness to the preference of citizens. As noble as these ideals are, upon their implementation,
­ the political as well as the economic environment in Africa was not conducive for them. Owing to this, when African nations adopted these alien principles they simply became democracies without being democratic.

Nonetheless, African nations are not the only ones in the world that had to succumb to a political system that is not inherently theirs. There are other non-western nations that espoused democracy and made it work. In his insightful research T.J Pempel (1992) proved this fact via his assessment of Japan’s remarkable success with democracy. In his research, he highlights how Japan is up to par with successful western industrialized democracies in most measurements of a good democracy. He shows how the country resembles the other advanced industrial democracies in most of its political and social institutions and behavioral traits irrespective of the fact that democracy isn’t Japanese in origin. Intriguingly, Pempel attributes this success to the Confucian cultural heritage, admirable work ethic, the egalitarian as well as the strong sense of civic mindedness embedded in the Japanese culture. Therefore, nations like Japan indubitably illustrate that an alien idea isn’t doomed to failure simply because it isn’t intrinsic to the society that adopts it.
Adversely, democracy failed miserably in Africa. Contrary to popular belief however, it didn’t fail because it was imposed by the west but because Africa did not have the culture to sustain its requirements; its requirements being the values of tolerance, efficacy, civility and civic mindedness. Albeit there could have been a meager chance for democracy to thrive in the African pre-colonial setting, (considering a lot of democratic values were infused in their fabric), the vile colonial and anticolonial legacies insured its death right after its birth.
As a result, during the time of decolonization,­ the grave mistake of planting democratic norms under the protest setting was committed. The byproduct of democracy that was achieved during freedom hence emphasized on unquestioned consensus as opposed to tolerance, on blind loyalty in contrast to self expression, on a myriad of group identities and not on individual rights and on political boundaries, strict dos and don’ts but hardly on procedures (Chazan, 1994: 17). This inevitably happened because democracy was instilled in an environment of resistance. As Namoi Chazan precisely expressed it, democracy in the African arena most frequently appeared as the political culture of “counter hegemony”. Such sentiments tainted its prospects in thriving right from the start. Elaborately:

“These circumstances could hardly have been less propitious for the entrenchment of liberal political cultures. Formal democratic institutions quickly collapsed under the weight of corruption and intolerance of dissent and state power was expanded, centralized personalized and corrupted. In the absence of broad political legitimacy, patterns of statism, patrimonial rule, abuse and political repression became entrenched with governments changing mainly through violence and democracy continuing to manifest itself as protest and resistance” (ibid).

Thus, democracy at best became gradual, messy, fitful and slow and at worst nonexistent. Crawford Young concluded it all in saying, “in no other world region has the third wave encountered so hostile an economic and political environment” (cited in Vicky and Svasand, 2002:31). As time passed, external presentability seemed to drive political reform rather than genuine commitment to liberalization hence the imperative, “virtual democracy” (Joseph, 1997:367).
---------------­-----------
Continuity within Change

During the euphoria of “the third wave of democratization­” major measures were taken to transform African nations from single party authoritarianis­m to multiparty democracy. Evidently, satirical titles in the likes of “president for life” were abolished via constitutional term limits for presidents. Legal institutions, parliaments and periodic elections became the norm rather than the exception. However, appearances can be deceiving as the changes were more cosmetic than real. Even nations that appeared democratic at first glance were characterized by “democratic rollbacks”, “democratic recession” or “democratic reversals”. Once elites got foothold of the state, they regressed to the personalized way of ruling just like the regime that preceded them ( Lynch and Crawford, 2011:278-282, Diamond 2008: 36-48). Hence, the predatory and neopatrimonial nature of African states made the established institutions ceremonial with no apparent functionality. Yet again, attesting to the strangeness of African politics, African nation’s integrated two types of systems popularly believed to be incompatible. Therefore, the supposedly rejuvenated African nations simply became wolf in sheep’s clothing.

Palpably, despite the fact that constitutional and other reforms were undertaken, it didn’t bring about viably attestable changes. The fact of the matter is: regardless of the constitutional arrangement “throughout the region, power is highly centralized around the president. “Africa’s current presidents may be term limited but by all accounts they have not yet been tamed” (Prempeh, 2008:110). They are literally above the law, control in many cases a large proportion of state finance with little accountability and delegate remarkably little of their authority on important matters (van de Walle, 2003:310). Presidents and their clients thus use the law to their advantage. Irrespective of their abundant presence the plethora of opposition parties rarely get elected into the national legislation, let alone take over power
Strangely, constitutional design has helped to ensure presidential dominance over the legislature, presidents extending nearly all non-legislative­ constitutional and statutory office. In addition, the power “to originate legislation including the all-important national budget is the exclusive prerogative of the executive in nearly all African constitutions; the legislature’s role is typically limited to approving or rejecting (but not amending) the executive’s budget and legislative proposals” (Prempeh, 2008:115).

Judiciaries across Africa suffer from many of the same handicaps that undermine legislative effectiveness. The finance ministry’s control of the treasury, which in many African countries has been reinforced by “cash –budget” laws, places the judiciary at the financial mercy of the executive (ibid: 118, Ellett, 2008, Odhiambo, 2012, Mzikamanda, 2007, Stokke et al. 2001:13). Due to the gross underfunding of the courts, chief justices often explore informal means of building the court’s influence with the executive in order to obtain the resources necessary to keep the courts functioning turning top jurists into politicians (ibid).

Moreover, even though a lot of African nations invariably claim that they delegate authority and share power, the reality is, the influential political elite isn’t only exceptionally a narrow one but almost entirely based in the capital city (van de Walle, 2003:310).Peopl­e are given political space, not to integrate them into the democratic polity but to separate them from meaningful participation at the national level; the granting of local authority is not a liberty but a constraint (Ibid) . Such systematic alienation underlines the confinement of local people and their disenfranchisem­ent; in reality initiatives and directives flow from the central to the local government in a strictly one-way traffic (Ake, 1991:37).
Overall, in such an environment where the judiciary has minimal independence and where there is a dearth in the rule of law and meaningful check and balance, “presidentialis­m” (van de Walle, 2003) or in other words, “personal rule” (Jackson and Rosberg, 1984) grew to dominate post 1990 African politics. “Webs of personalized circuits of distribution reciprocated with clientelist loyalty, created a honeycomb of networks by which the ascendancy of the ruler was maintained”(You­ng, 2004:35). Genuine concern for societal well being and free and fair elections were pushed to the sideline and democracy became a mere tomfoolery. When all is said and done, it is easy to deduce, the narcissistic and predatory African elites “have generally found little incentive to initiate reform beyond those limited rule changes deemed necessary to restore democratic accountability and placate external financiers” (Prempeh, 2008:111).
(Editorial Note- The NEVIS editorial team would like to thank Hiwot for her initiative. The section below is a continuation of what we have presented in NEVIS Review No 5)

Monday, December 3, 2012

NEVIS REVIEW No 5, Sec I, Part B ; Ref # 5.1.(B)



NEVIS REVIEW No 5
Section I 
Ref# 5.1.(B)
Dec 3, 2012

Political culture
(Part B) Political culture: General theoretical framework
POLITICAL CULTURE

Although insights into political culture have been part of political reflection since classical antiquity, two developments in the context of the French Revolution laid the groundwork for modern understandings. First, when members of the Third Estate declared “We are the people,” they were overturning centuries of thought about political power, captured most succinctly by Louis XIV’s infamous definition of absolutism: “L’etat, c’est moi ” (“I am the State”). Henceforth, sovereignty was seen to reside in society rather than in the monarch and his divine rights. A century later, Max Weber turned this political claim into a scientific one when he defined legitimacy as that which is considered to be legitimate—not only by elites but by the population in general; to understand the political power of the state, social science must therefore attend to its reception and sources in society. Second, when Jean-Jacques Rousseau retheorized the social contract as one in which individual interests were taken up in an overarching “General Will” of the collectivity, he raised the question of how social solidarity could be maintained in the absence of recourse to divine right. His answer was “civil religion,” symbols and rituals that establish and dramatize the sense of collective belonging and purpose. A century later, Émile Durkheim took up these themes when he questioned whether modern, complex societies could generate sufficient solidarity to function in a stable manner. Durkheim’s interest in what he called collective effervescence (generated in and through communal rituals) and collective representations (embodied in symbols as well as more abstractly in “collective conscience”) extended Rousseau’s concerns and has underwritten con-temporary analyses of political culture as the sets of symbols and meanings involved in securing and exercising political power.

Contemporary work on political culture, however, dates more directly to the mid-twentieth century, particularly in the United States. In the wake of World War II (1939–1945), social scientists were motivated to explain why some nations had turned to authoritarianism while others supported democratic institutions. Before and during the war, anthropologists such as Margaret Mead and Ruth Benedict were proponents of a “culture and personality” approach, which asserted that members of different societies develop different modal personalities, which in turn can explain support for different kinds of political programs and institutions. In a somewhat different vein, the German exile philosopher Theodor Adorno and colleagues undertook a massive study during the war into what they called, in the title of their 1950 work, The Authoritarian Personality, continuing earlier research by critical theorists into the structure of authority in families, which they believed had led Germans to support authoritarian politics and social prejudice. In a similar vein, Harold Laswell described a set of personality traits shared by “democrats,” including an “open ego,” a combination of value-orientations, and generalized trust.

Perhaps the most important work on political culture in this period was Gabriel Almond and Sidney Verba’s 1963 The Civic Culture: Political Attitudes and Democracy in Five Nations, which combined Laswell’s description of the democratic personality with at least two strands of social science theory at the time. First, the predominant sociological theory in the United States was that of Talcott Parsons, who explained social order in terms of institutions that inculcated individuals with coherent sets of norms, values, and attitudes—what Parsons called culture— which in turn sustained those institutions through time. In contrast, the so-called behavioral revolution in political science argued that such accounts neglected extra-institutional variables as sources of social order (a concern that could be traced back to Montesquieu in the mid-eighteenth century, who sought external factors—in his case climate—to explain the different forms of law in history); in Parsons, moreover, critics charged that norms, values, and attitudes were more often simply assumed as necessary integrative features of social systems rather than measured empirically (hence the appeal to behaviorism, which in psychology held observability to be the only relevant criterion for science).

The major point of Almond and Verba’s comparative study was to address the role of subjective values and attitudes of national populations in the stability of democratic regimes. This fit clearly within the behavioral revolution because it turned to extra-institutional variables (norms values, and attitudes) to explain political outcomes. Nonetheless, the work was presented as a study of political culture, defined as the aggregate pattern of subjective political dispositions in the populace, thus incorporating and, indeed, operationalizing, the Parsonsian concept of culture. On the basis of extensive survey research, The Civic Culture theorized three basic orientations toward political institutions and outcomes: parochial, where politics is not differentiated as a distinct sphere of life and is of relatively little interest; subject, in which individuals are aware of the political system and its outcomes but are relatively passive; and participant, where citizens have a strong sense of their role in politics and responsibility for it. The Civic Culture rated five countries on these qualities, finding Italy and Mexico to be relatively parochial, Germany to be subject, and the United States and the United Kingdom to be participant political cultures.

Subsequent work in this tradition by Ronald Ingelhart and others has shown that the effect of basic satisfaction with political life and high levels of interpersonal trust (what would later be called “social capital”) are analytically distinct from economic affluence, thus arguing forcefully that democracy depends on cultural as well as economic factors. Contemporary authors such as Samuel Huntington have extended this kind of argument about norms, values, and attitudes to the world stage, where they describe a “clash of civilizations” in terms of basic “cultural” differences understood in this way.

Nevertheless, there have been many criticisms of the approach developed by Almond and Verba and their colleagues. These ranged from methodological concerns about the survey instruments to the claim that the approach normatively privileged American-style democracy as the model against which all others must be judged. Still others argued that political culture was being used as a residual category for all that cannot be explained by other theories, and thus has no theoretically defensible conceptual ground of its own. Most trenchant, however, were charges that the way Almond and Verba defined political culture—in terms of subjectivity—eviscerates the importance of culture as symbols and meanings: Without a richer understanding of symbols, meanings, rituals, and the like, critics charged, political culture could not be distinguished conceptually from political psychology: “What ‘theory’ may be found in anyone’s head is not, ” one set of critics charged, “culture. Culture is interpersonal, covering a range of such theory.… Political culture is the property of a collectivity” (Elkins and Simeon 1979, pp. 128–129).

Indeed, since the 1970s, political culture theory has been radically transformed by a more general cultural turn in social science, brought about by such influences as the symbolic anthropology of Clifford Geertz and the rise of semiotics, structuralism, and poststructuralism in European anthropology and literary theory. In contrast to older subjectivism, as well as to those who ignore culture altogether, newer work on political culture in the 1980s and 1990s argued that, in Geertz’s words, “culture is public because meaning is” (Geertz 1973, p. 12). This work reformulated political culture as a system of meanings sui generis, as “a form of structure in its own right, constituted autonomously through series of relationships among cultural elements” (Somers 1995, p. 131), or as “codes,” which could be either manifest or “deep.” In this view, political culture can be measured only crudely by survey analysis; instead, it must be excavated, observed, and interpreted in its own terms as an objective structure, on the analogy of language.

However, the rise of various structuralisms in political culture analysis—emphasizing the Rousseau- Durkheim more than the Montesquieu-Weber axis—has required some modifications since the 1990s, when structuralist approaches in general have fallen somewhat out of favor. More recently, many historians, sociologists, and anthropologists have embraced a “practice” approach that emphasizes meaning making rather than meaning systems. While in no way a return to the earlier subjectivism in political culture theory, the practice approach recognizes the limitations of structuralism, in which agents seem to drop out of the picture, or serve only as enactors or carriers of structure. Instead, recent work has emphasized “the activity through which individuals and groups in any society articulate, negotiate, implement, and enforce competing claims they make upon one another and upon the whole. Political culture is, in this sense, the set of discourses or symbolic practices by which these claims are made” (Baker 1990, p. 4).
In sum, political culture theory makes empirical sense out of the French Revolution’s claim that sovereignty derives from society rather than the state. One temptation with this recognition, however, is to assume that while states are about power, societies are about meaning and the reception of power. One solution, inspired by Michel Foucault, among others, has been to declare society the true locus of power. The problem is that this misses the ways in which states do indeed set agendas for societies. Recent analyses have thus returned to the political culture of the state (e.g., Bonnell 1997). But they do so without supposing that societies are mere recipients of such productions.

In contrast to much work in political sociology, which has drawn a facile distinction between “merely” symbolic politics and “real” politics, recent political culture theory has thus demonstrated that social life is an ongoing reproductive process. New political culture analysts in particular have focused not only on how political acts succeed or fail to obtain some material advantage but also on how in doing so they produce, reproduce, or change identities. The struggle for position that constitutes politics, we now understand, is always simultaneously strategic and constitutive: As Lynn Hunt has written, “Political symbols and rituals were not metaphors of power; they were the means and ends of power itself” (Hunt 1984, p. 54). Interpreting them and understanding how they are generated and how they work is thus of paramount importance.
( Source- INTERNATIONAL ENCYCLOPEDIA OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES, 2ND EDITION)

NEVIS REVIEW No 5, Section II: Ref # 5.2



NEVIS REVIEW No 5
Section II
Ref# 5.2
Dec 3, 2012

From Liberation Movement to Government : Past legacies and the challenge of transition in Africa” by Christopher Clapham:
Summary by NEVIS editor, Mesfin Tekle
-------------------------
All those who struggled against oppression and autocratic governments are defined by the sacrifices they made to free the populous from a dictator or in South Africa’s case from racial domination by a minority. There are struggles for statehood such as in Eritrea and South Sudan or to overthrow a dictatorial regime in Ethiopia and Uganda. Clapham points out that once these liberation movements achieve victory and become a government “the experience of struggle has generally been regarded as an enormously positive legacy for the new state and the regime that rules it. The more intense the struggle, indeed, the greater the advantages conferred on the new government”. We can see the evidence of this in Ethiopia, Eritrea, Uganda, and South Africa. Here we should pose and ask a legitimate question. Are liberation movements entitled to govern ad infinitum? There are governments like that of Eritrea who still act like a liberation movement not a government. There are also governments who still feel entitled to govern forever. The “failure to move beyond ‘liberation politics’ and shed a struggle mindset” also results in a standoff with those who want to move on to the next level of governance that is not stuck in past grudges. In some of the states that have failed to live up to expectations, as problems mount “it becomes all too easy to view the legacies of the struggle not as a blessing but as a curse and to envy those countries whose transition to majority rule has been marked instead by peace and continuity”. All struggles have their unique characteristics that differentiate them from one another but what is striking is the recurring similarities that are common to most of them.
-----------------
The legacy of liberation

For those who go through the struggle and win “It brings with it a deep sense of conviction in the rightness of the cause, and the entitlement and responsibility of the survivors to continue to exercise the power, and pursue the objectives, for which they fought”. What has remained constant in most states that are governed by liberation movements is “a virtually permanent claim on state power: those who did not participate in their struggle, including those who were too young to have had any chance of doing so, are expected to take second place to veterans”. However, these same liberation movements forget that they also got to where they are today by suppressing dissent within their own organization or outside of it. “One common feature of liberation war is the contest for ‘movement hegemony’, in the course of which often vicious fighting takes place between rival movements”. TPLF Vs EPRP or ELF vs EPLF are good examples
--------------------

The challenge of Governance

“The moment at which a liberation movement comes to power is normally one of extraordinary catharsis”. Whatever misgivings the population has about the victors, the finality of the war in itself is welcome news to most of the citizenry. However, creating national reconciliation and forging forward for legitimacy was not an easy task to most of the victors. “Yoweri Museveni in Uganda or Meles Zenawi in Ethiopia – deliberately created new political structures intended to extend the legitimacy of the new regime beyond the limited areas of the country in which the war had been fought, and provide the basis for a new constitutional order”. However, running a government is a completely different exercise than leading a liberation movement. Governing requires accommodating varying interest groups whose interests might be at odds with each other. It is unlike fighting a regime with single-minded purposefulness. “Flexibility must replace rigidity”. Those like TPLF that took over a state apparatus and have to work with it were more successful than those like EPLF who chased out those who served the old regime regardless of the benefit that may have arisen by keeping them.
-----------------
Conclusion
Calpham in the end concludes that there is not single liberation movement that has transitioned seamlessly to a national government. Governance presents its own challenge that is not only unique but often conflicts with the principles of a liberation struggle that has led it to victory.
(For full article, you can check out this link http://www.thebrenthurstfoundation.org/files/Brenthurst_Commisioned_Reports/Brenthurst-paper-201208-From-Liberation-Movement-to-Government.pdf)

NEVIS REVIEW NO 5 Sec I, Part A; Ref # 5.1.(A)



NEVIS REVIEW  NO 5
Section I: Political culture-(Part A)
Ref # 5.1.(A)
Dec 3, 2012

Democracy and Political Culture: Part One
By Hiwot Wendimagegn

Ever since the demise of communism, democracy has attained prominence in virtually every nation of the world. Nations take pride in using this term in some form or another to describe themselves irrespective of their widely differing political social and economic systems. “ “People’s democracies, “revolutionary democracies”, “capitalist democracies”, “democratic republics”, “ liberal democracies”, “representative democracies” and “federal democracies” are but a few of the terminologies one could cite as evidence” (Pempel, 1992:5). Be that as it may, “these favorable opinions are often superficial and unless they are accompanied by deeper-rooted orientations towards tolerance, trust and a participatory outlook the chances are poor that effective democracy will be present at the societal level” (Inglehart and Welzel, 2003:62).

Evidently, most developing countries which claim to be democracies are far from being democratic. By the 1990’s, observers from Latin America, Eastern Europe to East Asia were concluding that cultural factors played an important role in problems they were encountering with democratization. In these nations, and others like them (African nations), the mere presence of democratic constitutions and democratic institutions could not bring about democracy (Joseph, 2002: 241-62, Prempeh, 2008, Tessler and Ebru, 2004: 21-50, van de Walle, 2003 Young, 2004:31 …etc). The Guatemalan sociologist Bernando Arevalo astutely expressed the semblance of democracy in his country by saying, “we have the hardware of democracy but the software of authoritarianism” (cited in Huntington and Harrison (eds), 2000).
Thereof, one of the main purposes of the study of political culture is determining the attitudes and values that foster democracy. Prominent theories of democracy both classic and modern have asserted that, democracy requires a distinctive set of political values and orientations from its citizens. These peculiar political values in the likes of civility, tolerance moderation and participation enhance the development and maturity of democracy, while their absence impairs it (Almond and Verba, 1963, Diamond, 1980:14-28, Pennock, 1979:236-259, Putnam, 1993, Pye, 1985….etc). Although a lot of attitudinal values could be pointed out as vehicles or obstacles of democracy, for the purpose of this article the concepts of “amoral familism” and “survival versus self expression values” are focused on.
------------------------------------------

Amoral Familism
In “The Republic”, Plato famously discusses about the family as the force underlying institutionalized social class and ascription. He asserted, the inherent relations among family members especially parents and children press them to make particularistic preferences that benefits the family even if the preferences require that they harm others. The opposite of particularism being universalism, the commitment to treat others according to similar standards, Plato cleverly concluded; to create an egalitarian society, the family itself has to be abolished and that children should be reared from birth in public institutions not knowing their parents (Plato, 1992: Chapter 5).
Two and a half millennia later, Edward Banfield modified Plato’s idea and introduced the concept of ‘amoral familism’ in his 1958 work, “The Moral Basis of a Backward Society”. Simply defined, amoral familism is “the felt obligation to help, to give resources to persons to whom one has a personal obligation, to the family above all, but also to friends and membership groups” (Lipset and Lenz, 2000:119). He used this concept to describe his observation of cities of Southern Italy, a self centric society which sacrificed the public good for the sake of nepotism.
In a similar vein, Putnam (1993) put forward the idea that a national culture of strong family ties generates extremely persistent distrust in government and parties. In his assessment of the Mafia, Putnam also established the negative sides of social capital which thwart societal well being. Such cooperation occurs among group members who are devotedly loyal to one another; forlornly, they care less about the rest of society. Good examples for such alliances are the Mafia, Hell’s Angels, Bandidos, the Skinheads, and the Ku Klux Klan.
After their thorough observation and empirical experimentation, Banfield, Putnam and others concluded, the backwardness of societies that mirror cities like Southern Italy could be explained largely by the inability of the citizens to act together for the common good or any end transcending the immediate, material interests of the nuclear family or particular groupings (Banfield, 1958, Galtung, 1974, Giuliano and Alberto, 2008, Putnam, 1993…etc). “Amoral familism prevents the development of well functioning political institutions, creates a situation where politics is simply a private affair of those who control it, common goods are completely disregarded and there is little interest in participating in public affairs” (Giuliano and Alberto, 2008:2).
All in all, extreme self-interestedness hinders democracy. “In a society that exhibits such tendencies, there is little loyalty to the larger community or acceptance of behavioral norms that require support of others. Hence, familism is amoral, gives rise to corruption and fosters deviance from norms of universalism and merit” (Huntington and Harrison (eds), 2000:120). To flourish and to persist, democracy requires a society that exhibits interpersonal trust, tolerance and participation in decision making. Such sentiments and behavioral patterns are unlikely to occur in a nation filled with groups that are at best antagonistic and at worst enemies.
--------------------------------
Survival versus Self Expression Values

The emergence of the post- industrial world has brought about a wave of cultural change. One such change is the shift from survival values to self expression values especially in 1st and 2nd world countries (Inglehart, 1971, 1997). The wealth that has accumulated in such advanced societies means that an increasing share of the population grows up taking survival for granted. Thus, priorities have shifted from an overwhelming emphasis on economic and physical security towards an increasing emphasis on subjective well being, self expression and quality of life (Ibid, Inglehart and Welzel, 2003, Huntington and Harrison (eds), 2000: 84-87). Such a shift diminishes social constraints in unprecedented ways, is thus one of emancipation from extreme and oppressive authority (Inglehart and Welzel, 2005).
Elaborately, survival values are characteristic of a society that prioritizes physical survival and economic well being above all else. “Societies that emphasize survival values show relatively low levels of subjective well being, report relatively poor health, are low in interpersonal trust, are relatively intolerant toward out groups, (…) emphasize materialist values (…) and are relatively favorable to authoritarian governments” (Huntington and Harrison (eds), 2000:85).
On the other hand, “Self expression values are a syndrome of mass attitudes that tap a common underlying dimension, reflecting emphasis on freedom, tolerance of diversity, and participation at both the individual and aggregate levels” (Inglehart and Welzel, 2003:64). Self expression values are present in a political culture in so far as the public emphasizes liberty and participation, self expression, tolerance of diversity, interpersonal trust and life satisfaction (ibid,). In analyzing data from the 1981 World Values Survey, Inglehart found that societies with relatively high levels of interpersonal trust and life satisfaction were more likely to have democratic institutions than societies with relatively low levels of trust and well being (Ibid:74).

As documented by many empirical evidences, democracy requires the presence of self expression values as opposed to survival values ; self expression values enhance democratization while survival values hinder it. Survival values are often held by poor nations which helps explain why richer societies are more likely to be democracies (Huntington and Harrison (eds), 2000:81). “People must be educated and fed before they can appreciate democracy, for there is no choice in ignorance and there are no possibilities for self fulfillment in extreme poverty” (Joseph, 2002:35).